Preamble: This is an
adaptation of the second chapter of my doctoral thesis (Inequality and Sustainability), which was supervised by
Professor JC (Jack) Caldwell, a co-recipient of the 2004 UN Population Prize. It
was awarded the Borrie Prize by the Australian Population
Association (APA) in 2002.
This essay
traces the rise and fall of Malthusian thinking within demography. Despite
winning the Borrie Prize, versions of this paper were rejected by many demographic
journals, include the Journal of Population Research (the APA’s
journal), the Population and Development Review and at least five more. Today,
despite having successfully published at least 50 articles, chapters and
reports of relevance to global population dynamics, I have not yet been
published in a primarily demographic journal. I share Maurice
King’s opinion that mainstream demography has been corrupted by
neoliberal forces who deny limits to growth, not only physical but social.
I have added a comment today (2017) about the figure, shown in PURPLE CAPITAL LETTERS
The concept of
non-human carrying capacity -- the population of a species supportable by a
given set of resources -- is a commonplace, generally accepted and understood
not only by ecologists but also by the general public. Yet the related topic of
human carrying capacity, though once also widely accepted, has in recent
decades received little attention among demographers and economists. The recent
reluctance by demographers to contribute to this debate, though heir to an
intellectual tradition containing much that is relevant to it, is regrettable,
and undermines the credibility of global population scenarios forecast by
demographers.
The suggestion
proposed by some “cornucopian” economists that humans, unlike other animal
species, can indefinitely evade carrying capacity limits has no basis. The
agnosticism of most demographers regarding this debate does a disservice to
demography and increases the risk of highly undesirable future global
population scenarios.
Introduction
The concept of a limited carrying capacity for non-human species was
once widely accepted by ecologists (Klein, 1968)[1] and the
general public. While aspects of it became controversial from the 1950s its
most important element – that of limits to growth – remains unchallenged.
Although it has fallen into some Indeed, this appreciation is not a uniquely
human characteristic, but intuitively appreciated, though of course not
verbalised, by all territorial species (Boehm, 1999).[2] Likewise,
this concept must also have been long understood by our own species, since the
time that bands of humans first explored new territories and were rewarded by
the discovery of less-exploited resources further along the coast or across the
sea (Flannery, 1994).
The concept of human carrying capacity – the maximum human
population supportable over a prolonged period by a given set of resources,
including human ingenuity and knowledge – appears, until recently, to have also
been well understood and accepted by many in both the general public and the
academy. In the last few decades, the influence of this school of thought has
become increasingly marginal, especially among social scientists.
The best-known author in this field in recent years is the ecologist
Paul Ehrlich (Ehrlich, 1968; Ehrlich and Ehrlich, 1990; Ehrlich et al.,
1995). Many mainstream social scientists, particularly economists, have at
times ridiculed Ehrlich’s position, characterising him and his supporters as
“doomsayers” (Kasun, 1988; Economist, 1994). The discipline of ecological
economics is an important exception (Arrow et al., 1995), but though
intellectually robust (Daly and Cobb, 1989; Daly, 1996) it remains politically
uninfluential (Butler et al., 2001). Few demographers now treat or study
the issue of global human carrying capacity seriously, despite the privileged
position accorded to this profession in its preparation of future global
population scenarios (United Nations Population Division Department of Economic
and Social Affairs, 2001).
Global human carrying capacity
No credible writer on the subject of human carrying capacity denies that
it is elastic. An irrefutable example of this elasticity is the massive
increase in human population in the last ten millennia made possible by
agriculture. More recently, the industrial and Green revolutions have enabled
substantially larger increases in both human population and global carrying
capacity. However, while further increases are likely, driven by ongoing
improvements in resource utilisation, ingenuity, social organisation and
technology (Boserup, 1965), it is far from certain that the marginal
increase in global carrying capacity will continue to exceed the marginal
demand placed upon it by additional people. Like a balloon, human carrying
capacity is elastic, but this does not mean its indefinite inflation is
possible.
The recent success at increasing global human carrying capacity has led
to a number of extreme claims. For example, the African Academy of Science, at
the New Delhi “Science Summit” on population in 1993 stated:
“Whether or not the Earth is finite will depend on the extent to which
science and technology is able to transform the resources available for
humanity. There is only one earth - yes, but the potential for transforming it
is not necessarily finite" (African Academy of Sciences, 1994)
(emphasis added).
Lawrence Summers, Under-Secretary in the US treasury in the Clinton
administration, exhibited a similar exuberance:
“There are
no...limits to the carrying capacity of the earth that are likely to bind any
time in the foreseeable future. There isn't a risk of an apocalypse due to
global warming or anything else. The idea that we should put limits on
growth, because of some natural limit, is a profound error and one that,
were it ever to prove influential, would have staggering social costs” (George
and Sabelli, 1994: 109) (emphasis added).
In fact, no matter how ingenious humans become, effective limits to the
maximum size of the human population will remain. As human population continues
to increase, within an earth system that is closed, evidence is increasingly
accruing to suggest that these limits are approaching. The limits that now seem
closest are not the exhaustion of easily recoverable trace elements, nor of
compressed, portable forms energy; concerns that were highlighted by the Limits
to Growth debate of the 1970s (Meadows et al., 1972; 1992). Instead, it
is increasingly clear that the capacity for the Earth system to absorb waste
products of human civilisation has been exceeded (Vitousek et al.,
1997a). For example, the atmospheric concentration of many greenhouse gases has
increased substantially. Carbon dioxide concentration has increased by a third
in the last two centuries, while that of methane has almost trebled.
Chlorofluorocarbons, a synthetic gas, have reduced the stratospheric ozone layer
by over 10% (Butler, 2000a). Though the fixing of atmospheric nitrogen, first
accomplished in 1913, greatly increased soil fertility and consequently the
human population (Meyer, 1996) many adverse ecological consequences of nitrogen
overload have also resulted (Vitousek et al., 1997b).[3]
Clearly, the Earth system is able to tolerate a substantial degree of
waste accumulation. Less certain is the degree to which this can continue
without commensurate damage to the human civilisation supported by the biosphere.
Waste products continue to accumulate, as do adverse ecological effects on a
global scale. For example, the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change has
predicted that global warming, consequent to the accumulation of waste
greenhouse gases, is likely to increase the average global temperature over the
next century by 1.4 to 5.8 degrees Celsius (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate
Change, 2001). Computer models (Knutson et al., 1998) and tentative
empirical evidence (Easterling et al., 2001) suggest this will be accompanied
by increasingly severe weather events, including more powerful storms and
stronger winds, an intensification of the El Niño Southern Oscillation cycle (Timmermann et al., 1999) and changing
patterns of drought and rainfall (Fischer et al., 2001). As well, global
sea level is predicted to increase by between 9 and 88 cms (Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change, 2001) over the next century.
These changes, resulting simply from climate change, are likely to have
profound adverse effects to the economy, especially to poor populations.
Although some optimists (Lomborg, 2001) contend that economic growth in the
next century will allow societies that are currently poor to successfully cope
with these additional stresses, there is a non-trivial possibility that the
reverse could occur. The ecological and environmental stresses predicted
consequent to “planetary overload” (McMichael, 1993) could trap many millions
of people into lives characterised by decreasing choices and increasing poverty.
Such “ecological entrapment” (Butler, 1997) seems particularly plausible
if recent global economic policies, characterised by increasing national and
global inequality (Butler, 2000a; Milanovic, 2002) continue. These policies
have been exacerbated by the abandonment of once widely-accepted aid targets
(Jha et al., 2002) and increased awareness, by the poor, of their relative
poverty. These factors may well lead to resentment, despair, and, ultimately,
mutually destructive attacks launched by excluded populations and their
supporters against populations perceived as wealthy, dominant, and exploitative
(Sachs, 2001; Butler, 2001a).
The rise and fall of Malthusianism
The disregard of the carrying capacity debate in recent decades by most
demographers is particularly surprising given that until recently it was a
central issue for population scientists. Many past scholars recognised and
discussed regional human carrying capacity, including in ancient Babylon, Rome,
Greece and China (Cohen, 1995; Demeny, 1988; Sallares, 1991). Ecclesiastes
(5:11) records that “when goods increase they are increased that eat them”. In
China, Hung Liang-Chi (1744-1809) wrote, independently of Thomas Malthus
(1766-1834), of population outstripping food supply, survival of the fittest,
and the reliance on the natural “checks” of flood, drought, plague, pestilence
and warfare to limit population growth (Silberman, 1960; Borrie, 1974).
In the western tradition, many of the concepts embedded in this debate
are known eponymously, as Malthusianism. Malthus’s main work An essay on the
principle of population (1798) predicted that population would grow
“geometrically” (in multiples) while food production would only grow
“arithmetically” (in additions). Thus, food production would never keep pace
with population growth. This pessimistic forecast was lightened by later
editions that allowed the possibility of “moral restraint”, including delayed
marriage, to slow population growth, rather than the checks of famine and war
(AtKisson, 1999; Boserup, 1978; Keyfitz 1993; Johnson, 1999a).
Malthus’s arguments had considerable influence, including to the theory
of evolution (Desmond and Moore, 1991: 264-265) and to British economic policy,
including its response to the Irish famine of the hungry 1840’s. Malthusian
thought dominated the population debate in Europe at least until the
“optimistic 1860s” (Boserup, 1978;
Desmond and Moore, 1991: 266), but persisted far longer in less
industrialised, low-income and famine-prone countries such as India (Caldwell,
1998).
Though never entirely absent, public concern over Malthusian arguments
diminished further in the 20th century. In that period, global
population increased almost fourfold, as innumerable technological advances not
only curtailed death rates, but also allowed food production to pull ahead of
population, at least temporarily. However, in the 1960s, fears of a global food
shortage resurged (Paddock and Paddock, 1967; Ehrlich, 1968). This period
experienced the maximum rate of global population increase (slightly over 2%
per annum) (United Nations Population Division Department of Economic and
Social Affairs, 1995: 99), a severe grain shortage in India (Brown, 2001;
Kasun, 1988) and a massive, though largely secret and man-made famine in China
(Smil, 1999). However, concerns rapidly abated in the following decade, as the
Green Revolution dramatically improved crop yields throughout much of the
world.
Perhaps as a sign of the widespread relief felt at the abatement of
these concerns, the agricultural scientist Norman Borlaug was awarded the 1970
Nobel Peace Prize for his work in promoting this revolution. But, in his
acceptance speech, Borlaug warned:
“The Green Revolution has won a temporary success in man's war against
hunger and deprivation; it has given man a breathing space. If fully
implemented, the revolution can provide sufficient food for sustenance during
the next three decades. But the frightening power of human
reproduction must also be curbed; otherwise the successes of The Green
Revolution will be ephemeral only” (Tribe, 1994: 16) (emphases added).
In the following decade, per capita global grain production continued to
rise and memory of Borlaug’s warning faded. China’s introduction of its one
child policy in 1979 imposed an accelerated demographic transition upon one
quarter of humanity.
In the US, the election of Ronald Reagan (1981) broke a chain of
presidents from J.F. Kennedy to Jimmy Carter (Kasun, 1988; Nixon, 1992; Finkle
and MacIntosh, 1994) each of whom[4] had
expressed grave concern about the rate and sustainability of Third World
population growth. In contrast, the Reagan administration was marked by a
progressive reduction in funding for Third World family planning programmes
(Kasun, 1988; Cincotta and Crane, 2001) and by increasingly influential
economic arguments that claimed to justify this position.
In the 1950s, the classic Malthusian scenario of rapid population growth
leading to food scarcity had been broadened to examine the relationship between
rapid population growth and economic growth. Influential publications by Nelson
(1956) and Leibenstein (1954; 1957) theorised that capital-poor governments and
populations struggling to provide the infrastructure needed to escape poverty
could instead be trapped in a negative feedback spiral, fuelled by excessively
rapid population growth. Nelson (1956) called this a “low level equilibrium
trap”.
The harmful effects of rapid population growth, especially in
capital-poor Third World countries, were widely accepted in the following
decades, and were an important cause of the one child policy introduced by
China in 1979 (Kane and Choi, 1999). However, in 1980, the conservative
economist Julian Simon attacked this theory in an article entitled There is
no low-level fertility and development trap (Simon, 1980). In 1986, a
report from the US National Academy of Sciences report substantially revised warnings issued by a previous report from 15 year
earlier. Importantly, this latter report claimed to discredit the
economic reasons that until then had underpinned concerns about rapid
population growth (Eberstadt, 1992).
Davidson has not only argued that economics is not a value free science,
but also likened the role of economists to priests, whose most valued role is
to assuage the guilt of those who are most powerful and wealthy:
“It is good to be rich. It is even better to feel good about it. Much of
the theoretical baggage associated with economic rationalism provided the
ethical justification for the credo of the 1980s... the real task of the
economic rationalist is the not the creation of wealth-it is to convince the
rich that their greed is the engine whose generation creates wealth for the
whole community”.
Similarly, it can be argued that the radically altered conclusions of
the 1986 National Academy Report were based on a substantially different set of
values to the previous report. In particular, the 1980s were characterised by a
significant change to the political right, with an ascendancy of neo-liberal
economic policies, particularly in the English speaking economies. A theory
advanced by Julian Simon and his supporters, though intellectually porous,
nevertheless served the purpose of assuaging the concerns of the public about
overpopulation in the Third World.
Essentially, this theory proposed that because every additional person
had two hands and a mind, laissez faire population growth and free trade
economic policies could help solve rather than hinder global development
(Simon, 1980; 1981; Simon and Kahn, 1984).[5] Though
vigorously attacked, including in several reviews in the Population and
Development Review (Serageldin and Kantner, 1982; Timmer, 1982) Simon’s arguments
were remarkably influential (Crane and Finkle, 1989; Beder, 1998).
Simon’s core argument dismissed or ignored many factors needed to
realise human potential. These include education, transport facilities, and
freedom from chronic diseases and certain kinds of pollution, especially in
childhood (Jha et al., 2002). For example, lead pollution, micronutrient
deficiency, especially of iodine and iron, and chronic caloric deficiency are
all associated with substantial falls in intelligence (Darnton-Hill, 1999;
Grantham-McGregor, 2002, Tong et al., 2000; Walgate, 2002). In
well-organised, functioning societies, nutrition can be improved, roads built,
and teachers trained. Societies can escape their poverty. But if infrastructure
deteriorates, if educated workers flee in large numbers to richer countries
seeking greater economic opportunity or to escape repression (Lwanda, 1998;
Pang et al., 2002) or if as many or more teachers die of HIV/AIDS than
graduate, then societies can spiral into a worsening cycle of entrapment (Piot,
2000).
Among the demographic community, the concept of entrapment lost favour,
becoming at best a footnote to a new generation of students and teachers. A
faint echo of this earlier view was recorded in 1992 by Panayotou:
“Where markets are not functioning, mobility is restricted, land and
wealth are skewedly distributed, and government policies counter or block the
avenues of individual and social response, a low-level trap is
artificially created where diminishing returns to land lead to resource
depletion and degradation, rather than to investment and innovation” (Cassen et
al., 1992).
Outside the demographic literature, the concept of entrapment was
revived, in a new form. In 1987 Lester Brown published a chapter called Analyzing
the demographic trap (Brown, 1987) and the same term (“demographic
entrapment”) was used by the eminent (King, 1967) public health worker Maurice
King, whose article Health is a sustainable state (King, 1990) was
published in the leading medical journal, The Lancet.[6] This and
many subsequent articles, published mainly in the European and Indian medical
and public health literature (King, 1990; 1991; 1999; Bonneaux 1994; Butler,
1994; 1997; 2000b; King and Elliott, 1996; 1997; McMichael and Powles, 1999;
McMichael et al., 1999) [7] were
highly controversial, fuelling a vigorous and still extant debate in the public
health literature (Abbasi, 1999). This
included proposals that significant conflict, including civil war, could
sometimes arise as a consequence of severe entrapment, and that the Rwandan
genocide represented such an example (Bonneaux 1994, Butler, 2000b).
These articles restated and expanded the economic entrapment theories of
the 1950s, but did not explicitly acknowledge this earlier literature.[8] Many of
King’s readers were probably unfamiliar with that literature; but, as an
important corollary, they were also ignorant of the 1986 National Academy
Report that had, ostensibly, discredited it (Eberstadt, 1992). Of crucial importance to the theme of this essay
is the fact that, outside the public health literature, this debate has
received scarcely any attention, not only from mainstream economists and
demographers, but even from most analysts of the Rwandan genocide (Butler, 2000a).
This has led King to postulate the existence of a profound intellectual
barrier, which he calls the “Hardinian taboo” (King and Elliot, 1997).
The population scientist, Joel Cohen’s book, How Many People can the
Earth Support provides a very rare exception, yet Cohen dismisses
demographic entrapment theory by using a cursory opinion by the economist
Robert Cassen (Cohen, 1995: 150). On the other hand, Cohen’s book amply
demonstrates the seriousness with which he treats the subject of human carrying
capacity, providing an extensive appendix on this topic.
Malthus and recent demographic agnosticism
Writing outside both the public health and demographic literatures, a
number of other scientists have also continued to worry about global human
carrying capacity. More than two decades after his original warning, Borlaug
stated that: “I am deeply concerned that humankind is being taken to the brink
of disaster in hopes that a scientific miracle at the last moment will save the
day” (Borlaug, 1995). The World Scientist’s Warning to Humanity,
originally issued in 1992, was signed by more than 1600 eminent scientists,
including over a hundred Nobel laureates (Kendall et al., 1995). Both it
and a similar document, called Population Growth, Resource Consumption and a
Sustainable World, jointly released by the US National Academy of Sciences
and The Royal Society (Atiyah and Press, 1992) warned of grave dangers if
population growth and patterns of human activity remain unchanged.
Paul Demeny, editor of the Population and Development Review, has
chastised his demographic colleagues for their recent abstinence from this
debate. For example, in 1988, Demeny wrote:
“Despite the pertinence of the concept to their discipline, most
demographers have tended to address the question of population carrying
capacity gingerly, if at all ... they have always been conscious that such
success (a rapid increase in human population size) cannot last long. To hammer
home this simple truth, a truth that should be evident, as Malthus noted ...
has been the time-honoured task of demographers. The demographic literature is
thus replete with reminders that population growth is a necessarily transitory
experience of the human species, but is rather short on specifics as to how
exactly long that passing moment in history may last” Demeny (1988: 216) (note
in brackets added).
In the following year, Demeny (1989) reviewed The Cassandra
Conference (Ehrlich and Holdren, 1988), a book based on a conference
that entirely presented neo-Malthusian arguments. In this, Demeny again
appealed for greater engagement by demographers with the wider debate
concerning human carrying capacity:
“A chapter in the book that should be obligatory reading for
demographers is Garret Harden's contribution ... Hardin present an honor list
of authors ‘whose works have contributed most to our understanding of
population.’ Demographers are conspicuous by their absence in the list. Save
for some exceptions, says Hardin, demographers either say nothing about the
human significance of the figures they play with, or they tell us ‘not to
worry’. They suffer from ‘pathological numeracy’. Apparently, no one rose
to dispute the charge. Had there been a card carrying demographer present, his rebuttal
to the ungallant diagnosis would have been probably less than vehement”
Demeny (1989) (emphases added).
Hardin, a human ecologist, supports the main argument of this paper,
that demographers have largely withdrawn from the neo-Malthusian debate. Hardin
goes further, by suggesting that many have adopted a patronising tone
concerning it. Demeny not only expresses sympathy with Hardin’s interpretation,
but also hints that he may be trying to use his position to advocate greater
engagement with these issues among demographers.
Joel Cohen, though dismissive of demographic entrapment, has also argued
that demographers need to widen their horizons to more explicitly consider
environmental issues. Cohen also has also referred to the demographer Kingsley
Davis in support, quoting him as complaining “no one specialises in the study
of population and resources as an integrated discipline” (Cohen, 1995:389).
Demeny has attempted to lead by example. Unfortunately, his most
rigorous attempt to consider the issue of global human carrying capacity, an
essay called Demography and the limits to growth (Demeny, 1988) suggests
a significant unfamiliarity with the relevant environmental literature.
Discussing the children’s riddle[9] used to illustrate the concept of exponential growth and the Limits
to Growth, perceived by Meadows et al., (1972) Demeny asks:
“How is to be
ascertained that we are on the 29th day and face the last chance ‘to save the
pond’? Diagnosis is a simple matter if what is required is to look at a
backyard lily pond, but is clearly less obvious in sizing up the state of the
global population. On what basis can we discard the conjecture that the present
corresponds, say, to the 24th day, when the global pond would be 1/64th full?”
(Demeny, 1988).
This question reveals an apparent ignorance of a then recently published
paper that had argued that the human
appropriation of the products of terrestrial photosynthesis already
approximated 40% (Vitousek et al., 1986). Demeny’s paper mainly focussed
upon responses to major limits to growth perceived a decade earlier,
particularly of raw minerals and energy. In the subsequent years the debate had
broadened, both to the capacity of the Earth system to absorb the waste
products of civilisation, such as greenhouse gases and ozone depleting
substances and, as Vitousek et al’s 1986 paper exemplifies, to estimates
of the global “footprint” upon the biosphere (Wackernagel and Rees, 1995).
Though Vitousek et al’s paper can be criticised as an heroic,
pioneering attempt, it remained, until the publication by Rojstaczer et al (2001), the
most authoritative publication on this subject.[10] In contrast to Demeny’s ignorance of this paper, Vitousek et al
(1986) not only explicitly referred to the proximity of a limit to global
growth implied by their findings, but also demonstrated familiarity with both
the cornucopian and demographic literature, citing Simon, Herman Kahn, and
Demeny himself.
Demeny’s failure to discuss this paper fuels speculation that, possessed
with a little more information, he may have more clearly expressed a
neo-Malthusian viewpoint than he did. Instead, both in this paper and a number
of book reviews (Demeny, 1982a; 1982b), Demeny settles on a position that,
though not cornucopian, is far more optimistic than that of the ecologists.
With few exceptions (Day and Day, 1965; Day and Rowland, 1988; Day,
1998), most mainstream demographers and economists have continued to write as
though the issue of global human carrying capacity is irrelevant in the
foreseeable future – as though the world might safely accommodate at least
another doubling of its population. A very recent exception to this is provided
by the demographer Jon Bongaarts, who provides a rephrasing of entrapment
theory:
“Rapid population
growth leads to a young population, one in which as much as half is below the
age of entry into the labor force. These young people have to be fed, housed,
clothed and educated, but they are not productive, thus constraining the
economy. Second, rapid population growth creates a huge demand for new jobs. A
large number of applicants for a limited number of jobs exert downward pressure
on wages, contributing to poverty and inequality. Unemployment is widespread,
and often workers in poor countries earn wages near the subsistence level. … This
points to another burden of rapid population growth: the inability of
governments to cope with large additions of new people. In many developing
countries, investments in education, health services and infrastructure are not
keeping up with population growth” (Bongaarts, 2002) (emphasis added).
Approaching the limits?
Several factors, acting synergistically, may soon force additional
demographers and economists to reconsider the relevance of global carrying
capacity. One is that, despite widespread denial of both its reality and
significance, the trend of the per capita global grain harvest appears to have
entered a period of sustained decline (see figure).
A second factor is that the increasing number of global refugees is
arguably related to the overloading of regional carrying capacity in many
impoverished parts of the world. Refugees, asylum seekers, and organised people
smugglers, driven by strong “push” and “pull” factors, are proving an
increasing problem for most wealthy countries. In addition, despite birth rates
that are well below population replacement in most developed countries, the
barriers to unskilled immigrants from poor population-surplus nations continue
to steepen. Few commentators have explicitly connected both the push and the
“block” factors to carrying capacity (Butler, 2001b).
Thirdly, as a consequence of climate and other global environmental
changes, themselves mostly brought about by “planetary overload” (McMichael,
1993), it is plausible that total global carrying capacity may actually decline
in the coming century, even if technology and agricultural yields continue to
improve. The most likely path for this is if, as some global climate simulators
predict, the agricultural capacity of the world changes markedly. Though most
writers on this subject have concluded that the total global food growing
potential capacity will remain roughly equivalent to today (Parry and
Rosenzweig, 1993; Dyson, 1999a; 1999b; Parry et al., 1999), I am unaware
of any that have discussed the implications of the marked shifts in regional
agricultural capacity predicted by most models.
For example, modellers at the International Institute of Applied Systems Analysis, have warned that,
by 2080, climate change may decrease agricultural capacity in large parts of
South Asia, Indonesia and Sub-Saharan Africa (Fischer et al., 2001). The
models suggest compensatory increased agricultural potential in parts of North
Asia and Canada. This scenario of winners and losers presents many problems.
Falling food production in densely populated tropical and sub-tropical
regions is likely to lead to widespread unemployment and hardship, especially
for subsistence farmers, and increased urbanisation. In addition, the areas
predicted to develop a more favourable agricultural climate (provided they also
have suitable soil characteristics) are largely situated in countries other
than those most likely to be adversely affected. Thus, farming populations made
redundant by climate change are unlikely to be able to easily migrate to the
virgin lands that changing weather patterns may open up for development. As
well, agricultural developments in these areas are likely to be more capital
intensive than those that are displaced, and thus unable to employ more than a
fraction of the displaced workforce, even if migration is possible.
Two issues are even more problematic. Populations disadvantaged by
climate change will not only need to generate sufficient funds to import food,
but the developers of the new land are likely to need a strong economic
incentive to do so. Finally, the climatic transition is unlikely to be
temporally smooth; that is to say, there may be periods when the climate limits
the harvest in both the new and old areas. This could lead to a significant
shortfall in global food supplies, with resultant political and economic
crisis.
While such a decline would not necessarily be catastrophic, it is likely
to require a greater willingness by powerful populations to share their wealth
than has been evident in recent decades (Butler, 2000a). At the worst case,
excessive selfishness by a privileged minority could provoke a form of a “global
guerrilla war” in which comparatively poor populations use increasingly
desperate and violent means to express their frustration. Indeed, the recent
terrorist attacks on the US, especially on September 11, 2001, can be
interpreted in this way (Butler, 2001b).
The global grain harvest
Data from the Food and Agricultural Organisation shows that the per
capita global grain harvest peaked in 1985. The significance of the decline in
the following decade has been extensively debated, but little attention has yet
been paid to the decline that has occurred in more recent years. Advocates in
this dispute have either expressed concern and called for more debate
(McMichael, 1995; King and Elliott, 1996) or taken the view that decline is
unimportant.
Supporters of the latter school have advanced two main arguments. Some
have claimed that the decline is an artefact caused by aberrant economic
factors in the mid-1980s and early 1990s (Dyson, 1999a; 1999b; Alexandratos,
1995; 1999; Ruttan, 1996). Others have suggested that even if the decline is
real, it is unimportant because of “Simpson’s paradox” (Alexandratos, 1999;
Johnson, 1999a; 1999b). This is that, using certain assumptions, it is possible
to demonstrate mathematically that grain consumption can increase for both
wealthy and poor populations, even if the average per capita global grain
consumption declines, provided an increasing percentage of the global
population is relatively poor.
Given the most sustained decline in the per capita grain harvest in each
of the last five years, the first argument looks increasingly vulnerable. There
are also plausible reasons for a decline in this indicator, other than the
withdrawal of subsidies that may have irrationally stimulated excessive
European grain production in the 1980s. Although grain yields are continuing to
improve, their rate of increase is slowing. This is in part because many of the
gains obtainable from easy fertilisation and irrigation of crops have already
been made. As well, theoretical limits to the efficiency of photosynthesis may
be approaching (Sheehy, 2001a). Finally, heat stress consequent to global
warming (Sheehy, 2001b) and soil degradation are also reducing yield increases
(Wood et al., 2000).
The second theory used to make the case that the fall in the per capita
harvest is benign is also problematic. Without more data, Simpson’s paradox
remains a speculative explanation. As well, it fails to explain why the paradox
did not apply in the years prior to 1985, when the increase in the global grain
harvest stayed comfortably ahead of population increase.
While it is true that the real international price of grain prices does
not yet suggest an impending grain shortage, the price is artificially
depressed by subsidies (Bongaarts, 2002). Furthermore, many poor populations
lack adequate food entitlement (Sen, 1981). That is, these populations are
unable to acquire sufficient money to generate effective demand. The size of this
population is very large. Already, about 33% of children aged under five years in developing countries
suffer moderate or severe growth retardation, and the prevalence rises to over
50% in some least-developed countries (Grantham-McGregor,
2002). This reflects chronic
under-nutrition, and demonstrates that the price of grain, even if low compared
to the purchasing power of wealthy populations, is too high for hundreds of
millions of people.
Figure 1. World per capita grain production
1966-2001.
The per capita global grain harvest has declined since its maximum in
1985. Preliminary data for 2001 suggests a further decline. Data Food and
Agricultural Organisation (2001), United Nations Population Division Department of Economic and Social
Affairs (2001)
COMMENT: GRAIN HARVESTS HAVE, TO DATE (2017) KEPT PACE
WITH POPULATION INCREASE AND THE NUMBER OF HUNGRY IS REPORTED TO HAVE DECLINED.
HOWEVER, HUNGER AND UNDERNUTRITION REMAIN IMMENSE, AND THE PROGRESS TOWARDS THE
MILLENNIUM DEVELOPMENT TARGET WAS OBSCURED BY A CHANGE IN THE WAY THE FAO
MEASURES HUNGER: SEE Butler CD. Revised hunger estimates accelerate
apparent progress towards the MDG hunger target. Global Food
Security. 2015;5:19-24.
Conclusion
An encouraging exception to the general silence expressed by most
demographers concerning global carrying capacity was recently provided by John
Bongaarts:
“Considerable uncertainty in projections stems from unexpected events.
Wars, natural disasters, economic crises, and similar events can generate
streams of migrants, suppress fertility temporarily, and produce many premature
deaths. On the positive side, unexpected biomedical breakthroughs may lead to large
increases in life expectancy or provide new fertility options. Environmental
crises that may loom in the future are an additional concern. Events of such
types are not within the competence of demographers to predict. Their
involvement in interdisciplinary work is essential to obtain a better
appreciation of the likelihood and demographic implications of such events
(Bongaarts et al., 2000) (emphasis added).
Though Bongaarts acknowledges that demographers are not trained to
competently predict environmental crises, his sentiment that demographers need
to seriously consider their possibility is refreshing, and would probably be
applauded by both Cohen and Demeny.[11]
However, the vast majority of demographers and non-ecological economists
have, in recent decades, ignored or greatly discounted human carrying capacity
issues. Instead, most of the social science community has assuming, either
explicitly or implicitly, that science, technology and free market economic
policies will provide ready answers to cope with resource scarcities and the
resulting tensions and conflicts likely to arise. This complacency is at odds
with the repeated warnings of numerous elite scientists and scientific bodies
(Atiyah and Press, 1992; Union of Concerned Scientists, 1992; 1997) who have
instead argued that the only safe way to ensure adequate global carrying
capacity is to reduce consumption levels and accelerate the global demographic
transition.
Bongaarts’ appeal for greater engagement with this debate by demographers
and economists warrants support. Bongaarts implies that demographers and
economists lack sufficient training and skills to fully to fully appreciate the
environmental literature relevant to global carrying capacity. A corollary of
this is that they also lack any credible license to claim that this literature
is invalid.
In recent decades, as public concern for overpopulation has diminished,
so too has funding for family planning and foreign aid programmes.
Collectively, the social science community bears substantial responsibility for
this. Closer co-operation and greater humility, by parties on both sides of
this debate are urgently needed if humanity is to safely traverse the shoals
that clearly face it.
References
Abbasi, K. 1999a.
King in a maverick style. BMJ 319, 942.
African Academy of
Sciences 1994. The African Academy of Sciences on population. Population and
Development Review 20, 238–239.
Alexandratos, N.,
(ed.) 1995. World Agriculture Twards 2010. John Wiley and Sons, Chichester,
UK., cited by Ruttan (1996) and Dyson, 1999a.
______ 1999. World food and agriculture: outlook for the medium and longer
term. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 96, 5908-5914.
Arrow, K., Bolin,
B., Costanza, R., Dasgupta, P., Folke, C., Holling, C.S., Jansson, N.-O.,
Levin, S., Mäler, K.-G.,
Perrings, C., and Pimental, D. 1995a. Economic growth, carrying capacity, and
the environment. Science 268, 520-521.
Atiyah, M., and
Press, F. 1992. Population Growth, Resource Consumption and a Sustainable
World. http://208.240.253.224/page7.htm . 31.5.01
AtKisson, A. 1999.
Believing Cassandra: An Optimist Looks at a Pessimist's World. Chelsea Green
Publishing Company, White River Jn, VT, USA.
Beder, S. 1998. Global
Spin: the Corporate Assault on Environmentalism. Scribe Publications,
Melbourne, Vic. Australia
Boehm, C. 1999.
Hierarchy in the Forest: the Evolution of Egalitarian Behaviour. Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA, USA.
Bongaarts, J. 2002 Population: ignoring its impact. Scientific
American 286 (1) 65-67.
______ , Bulatao, R.A., Panel on Population Projections, Committee on Population, National
Research Council, (Eds.) 2000.
Beyond six billion: forecasting the world's population., pp. 1-258. National
Academy Press, Washington DC, USA. www.nap.edu/books/ 0309069904/html/ 10.12.01
Bonneux, L. 1994.
Rwanda: a case of demographic entrapment. The Lancet 344, 1689-1690.
Borlaug, N.E. 1995.
Food Production. In: Meeting the Challenges of Population, Environment, and
Resources. The cost of inaction, Third Annual World Bank Conference on
Environmentally Sustainable Development. Union of Concerned Scientists and the
World Bank, Washington DC, pp. 16-18.
Borrie, J. B. 1974.
China's Population Struggle: Demographic Decisions of the People's Republic
1949-1969 [book review]. Demography 11, 702-705.
Boserup, E. 1965
The Conditions of Agricultural Growth: the Economics of Agrarian Change under
Population Pressure. Aldine Publishing Company, New York, NY, USA.
Boserup, M. 1978.
Fear of doomsday: past and present. Population and Development Review 4,
133-143.
Brown, L.R. 1987.
Analyzing the demographic trap. In: State of the World 1987, L. Brown, ed.
Norton, New York, NY, USA., pp. 20-37.
______ 2001. Eco-economy: Building an Economy for the Earth. W. W. Norton &
Co, New York, NY, USA
Butler, C.D. 1994.
Overpopulation, overconsumption, and economics. The Lancet 343, 582-584.
______ 1997. The consumption bomb. Medicine Conflict
and Survival 13, 209-218.
______ 2000a. Inequality, global change and the sustainability of civilisation.
Global Change and Human Health 1, 156-172.
______ 2000b. Entrapment: global ecological and/or local demographic?
Reflections upon reading the BMJ's "six billion day" special issue.
Ecosystem Health 6, 171-180.
______ 2001a. A world war against terrorism [letter]. The Lancet 358, 1366.
______ 2001b. The life of refugees [letter]. The Lancet 358, 1102.
______, Douglas, R. M., and McMichael, A. J. 2001. Globalisation and
environmental change: implications for health and health inequalities. In: The
Social Origins of Health and Well-being R. Eckersley, J. Dixon and B. Douglas,
(Eds.). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 34-50.
Cairns, J. 1999.
The quest for increased longevity on an unsustainable planet. Ecosystem Health
5, 67-69.
Caldwell, J.C.
1998. Malthus and the less developed world: the pivotal role of India.
Population and Development Review 24, 675-696.
Cassen, R. et al 1994. Population and Development Old Debates, New
Conclusions. New Brunswick, Transaction Publishers., cited by Eberstadt 1994
(pages 150 and 156).
Cincotta, R.P., and
Crane, B.B. 2001. The Mexico City policy and US family planning assistance.
Science 294, 525-526.
Cohen, J.E. 1995. How Many People can the Earth Support? W. W.Norton and Co, New
York, NY, USA.
Crane, B.B. and
Finkle, J.L. 1989. The United States, China
and the United Nations Population Fund: dynamics of US policy making.
Population and Development Review, 15, 23-59.
Daly, H.E. 1996.
Beyond Growth. Beacon Press, Boston, MA, USA.
______ and Cobb, J.B. 1989. For the Common Good. Beacon Press, Boston, MA, USA.
Day, L.H. 1998.
Maybe one: a personal and environmental argument for single-child families, B.
McKibben [book review]. Population and Development Review 24, 642–644.
______ and Day,
A.T. 1965. Too Many Americans. Dell, New York, NY, USA.
______ and Rowland, D.
T., (Eds.) 1988. How Many More Australians? : the Resource and Environmental conflicts. Longman Cheshire, Melbourne, Australia.
Darnton-Hill, I.
1999. The challenge to eliminate micronutrient malnutrition. Australia and New
Zealand Journal of Public Health 23, 309-314.
Davidson, K. 1992.
Defrocking the priests. In: The Trouble with Economic Rationalism D. Horne,
(ed). Scribe Publications, Melbourne, Vic, pp. 58-62.
Demeny, P. 1982a.
Review of Herman Kahn, The Coming Boom: Economic, Political, and Social
Population and Development Review 8, 852-856.
______ 1982b. Review of P.T. Bauer, Equality, the Third World, and Economic
Delusion. Population and Development Review 8, 191-193.
______ 1988. Demography and the limits to growth. Population and Development
Review 14, 213–244.
______ 1989. The Cassandra Conference: Resources and the Human Predicament. PR
Ehrlich, J Holdren [book review]. Population and Development Review 15,
574-575.
Desmond, A., and
Moore, J. 1991. Darwin. The Life and Times of a Tormented Evolutionist. W.W.
Norton, New York, NY, USA.
Dyson, T. 1999a.
Prospects for feeding the world. BMJ 319, 988-991.
______ 1999b. World food trends and prospects to 2025. Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences 96, 5929-5936.
Easterling, D. R.,
Meehl, G. A., Parmesan, C., Changnon, S. A., Karl, T. R., and Mearns, L. O.
2000. Climate Extremes: Observations, Modeling, and Impacts. Science 289,
2068-2074.
Eberstadt, N. Population and development old debates, new
conclusions [book reviews] Population and Development Review 21, 419-426.
Economist 1994.
Apocalypse soon. July 23, pp 29-30.
Ehrlich, P.R. 1968.
The Population Bomb. Ballantyne, New York, NY, USA.
______ and Holdren, J.P. 1988. The Cassandra conference. Resources and the human predicament Texas A
& M University Press, College Station, TX, USA.
______ and Ehrlich, A.H. The Population Explosion. Simon and Schuster, NY, USA
______ Ehrlich, A.H., and Daily, G.C. 1995. The Stork and the Plow. The Equity
Answer to the Human Dilemma. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT, USA.
Finkle, J.L., and
McIntosh, C.A. 1994. The new politics of population: conflict and consensus in
family planning. Population and Development Review 20, 3-34.
Fischer, G., Shah,
M., van Velthuizen, H. and Nachtergaele, F.O. 2001. Executive summary report: Global
Agro-ecological Assessment for Agriculture in the 21st century., International
Institute of Applied Systems Analysis. http://www.iiasa.ac.at/Admin/INF/recent-pubs/gaea/
5.1.02
Flannery, T.F.
1994. The Future Eaters. Reed Books, Melbourne, Vic, Australia.
Food and
Agriculture Organization of the United Nations). 2001. The State of Food and
Agriculture 2001. No 33., Rome, Italy.
George, S., and
Sabelli, F. 1994. Faith and credit. The World Bank's Secular Empire. Penguin,
London, UK
Grantham-McGregor,
S. 2002. Linear growth retardation and cognition [commentary]. The Lancet 359,
111-114.
Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change 2001. Summary for Policymakers Climate Change 2001: The
Scientific Basis. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Jha, P., Mills, A.,
Hanson, K., Kumaranayake, L., Conteh, L., Kurowski, C., Nguyen, S. N., Cruz, V.
O., Ranson, K., Vaz, L. M. E., Yu, S., Morton, O., and Sachs, J. D. 2002.
Improving the health of the global poor. Science 295, 2036-2039.
Johnson, D.G.
1999a. Feeding a World Population of
More Than Eight Billion People: a Challenge to Science, J.C. Waterlow, D.G.
Armstrong, L. Fowden, and R. Riley (eds.) [book review]. Population and
Development Review 25, 159-163.
______ 1999b.The growth of demand will limit output growth for food over the
next quarter century. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 96,
5915-5920.
Kane, P. and Choi,
C.Y. 1999 China's one child family
policy BMJ 319, 992-994.
Kandela, P. 1998. Medical
journals and human rights. The Lancet 352, supp 2, 7-12.
Kasun, J. 1988. The
War Against Population: The Economics and Ideology of Population Control.
Ignatius Press, San Francisco, CA, USA.
Kendall, H. W.,
Arrow, K. J., Borlaug, N. E., Ehrlich, P. R., Lederberg, J., Vargas, J. I.,
Watson, R. T., and Wilson, E. O. 1995. Meeting the Challenges of Population,
Environment, and Resources. The Cost of Inaction, Rep. No. 14. Union of
Concerned Scientists and the World Bank, Washington DC, USA.
Keyfitz, N. 1993.
Living Within Limits: Ecology, Economics, and Population Taboos, G. Hardin,
[book review] Population and Development Review 19, 859-863.
King, M.H., (ed.)
1966. Medical care in developing countries. A primer on the medicine of poverty
and a symposium from Makerere. Oxford University Press, Nairobi, Kenya.
______ 1990. Health is a sustainable state. The Lancet 336, 664-667.
______ 1991. Human entrapment in India. The National Medical Journal of India 4
196-201.
______ 1999. The US Department of State is policing the population policy
lockstep. BMJ 319, 998-1001.
______ 2001. AIDS is
making the disentrapment of Malawi possible.
http://www.leeds.ac.uk/demographic_entrapment/page25.htm 5.12.01
______ and Elliott, C. 1996. Averting a world food shortage: tighten your belts
for CAIRO II. BMJ 313, 995-997.
______ and Elliott, C. 1997. To the point of farce: a Martian view of the
Hardinian taboo - the silence that surrounds population control. BMJ 315,
1441-3.
Klein, D. R. 1968.
The introduction, increase, and crash of reindeer on St. Matthew Island.
Journal of Wildlife Management 32, 350-367.
Knutson, T. R.,
Tuleya, R. E., and Kurihara, Y. 1998. Simulated Increase of Hurricane
Intensities in a CO2-Warmed Climate. Science 279, 1018-1020.
Leibenstein, H. A 1954.
Theory of Economic-Demographic Development, Princeton University Press,
Princeton NJ, USA.
______ 1957. Economic Backwardness and Economic Growth. John Wiley and Sons,
New York, NY, USA.
Lomborg, B. 2001.
The Skeptical Environmentalist. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
McMichael, A. J.
1993. Planetary Overload. Global Environmental Change and the Health of the
Human Species. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
______ Contemplating a one child world. Falling
grain stocks and rising population spell disaster and demand debate. BMJ 311,
1651-1652.
______ and Powles, J.W. 1999. Human numbers, environment, sustainability, and
health. BMJ 319, 977-980.
______ , Guillebaud, J., and King, M. 1999. Contrasting views on human population
growth. One wisdom justifies complacency: the other demands action now
[editorial]. BMJ 319, 931-932.
Meadows, D.,
Meadows, D., Randers, J., and Behrens III, W. 1972. The Limits to Growth.
Universe Books, New York, NY, USA.
______ , Meadows, D., and Randers, J. 1992. Beyond the Limits: Global Collapse or
a Sustainable Future. Earthscan, London, UK.
Meyer, W. B. 1996.
Human Impact on the Earth. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Milanovic, B. 2002. World income distribution, 1988 and 1993:
First calculation based on household surveys alone. The Economic Journal 112,
51-92.
Nelson, R.R. 1956.
A theory of the low-level equilibrium trap in underdeveloped economies. The
American Economic Review 46, 894-908.
Ness, I., and
Ciment, J. D. 1999 The Encyclopaedia of Global Population and Demographics.
Fitzroy Dearborn Publishers, Chicago, Il, USA.
Nixon, R. 1992.
Richard Nixon on US assistance for population programs. Population and
Development Review 18, 378-379.
Paddock, W., and
Paddock, P. 1967. Famine 1975! America's Decision: Who will Survive? Little
Brown, Boston, MA, USA.
Parry, M. L., and
Rosenzweig, C. 1993. Food supply and risk of hunger. The Lancet 342, 1345-1347.
Parry, M. L.,
Rosenzweig, C., Iglesias, A., Fischer, G., and Livermore, M. 1999. Climate
change and world food security: a new assessment. Global Environmental Change
9, s51-s67.
Piot, P. 2000.
Global AIDS epidemic: time to turn the tide. Science 288, 2176-2178.
Rojstaczer, S.,
Sterling, S.M., and Moore, N.J. 2001. Human appropriation of photosynthesis
products. Science 204, 2549-2552.
Ruttan, V.W. 1996.
Review of Gordon Conway: The Doubly Green Revolution: Food for All in the
Twenty-first Century. Population and Development Review 24, 394-395.
Sachs, J. 2001.
Speech to forum 2000. .www.forum2000.cz 10.12.0
Sallares, R. 1991.
The Ecology of the Ancient Greek World. Duckworth, London, UK.
Sen, A.K. 1981.
Poverty and Famines: an Essay on Entitlement and Deprivation. Clarendon Press,
Oxford, UK.
Sheehy, J.E. 2001a. Future food
requirements: are improvements in photosynthesis required? 12th International
Congress on Photosynthesis, Brisbane Convention & Exhibition Centre,
Brisbane, Australia http://www.botany.uq.edu.au/ps2001/ 24.8.01
______ 2001b. The
consequences of global warming. International Rice Research Institute. http://www.irri.org/ar2001/sheehy2.pdf 2.12.01
Serageldin,
I., and Kantner, J. F. 1982. Review of Julian L.
Simon, The Ultimate Resource. Population and Development Review 8, 169-173.
Silberman, L. 1960.
Hung Liang-Chi: a Chinese Malthus. Population Studies 13, 257-265.
Simon, J.L. 1980.
There is no low-level fertility and development trap. Population Studies 34,
476-486.
______ 1981. The Ultimate Resource. Martin Robertson, Oxford, UK.
______ , and Kahn,
H. 1984. The Resourceful Earth. Blackwell, Oxford, UK.
Smil, V. 1999. China's great famine: 40 years later BMJ 319,
1619-1621.
Timmer, C. P. 1982.
Review of Julian L. Simon, The Ultimate Resource. Population and Development
Review 8, 163-168.
Timmermann, A.,
Oberhuber, J., Bacher, A., Esch, M., Latif, M., and Roeckner, E. 1999.
Increased El Niño frequency in a climate model forced by future greenhouse
warming. Nature 398, 694-697.
Tong, S.,
Prapamontol, T., and Schirnding, Y. v. 2000. Environmental lead exposure: a
public health problem of global dimensions. Bulletin of the World Health
Organisation 78, 1068-1077.
Tribe, D. 1994.
Feeding and Greening the World. CAB International in association with the
Crawford Fund for International Agricultural Research, Wallingford, UK.
Union of Concerned
Scientists 1992. World Scientists' Warning
to Humanity, Union of Concerned
Scientists, Cambridge, Mass., USA.
http://www.ucsusa.org/about/warning.html 14.01.01
Union of Concerned
Scientists 1997. World Scientists' Warning
to Humanity, Union of Concerned
Scientists, Cambridge, Mass., USA.
http://www.ucsusa.org 13.6.00
United Nations
Population Division Department of Economic and Social Affairs. 1995. World
Population Prospects: The 1994 Revision. United Nations, New York, NY, USA.
______ 2001. World Population Prospects: the 2000 revision. United Nations, New
York, NY, USA.
Vitousek, P.M.,
Ehrlich, P.R., Ehrlich, A.H., and Mateson, P.A. 1986. Human appropriation of
the products of photosynthesis. BioScience 34, 368-373.
______ , Mooney, H. A., Lubchenko, J., and Melillo, J. M. 1997a. Human
domination of the Earth's ecosystems. Science 277, 494-499.
______ , Aber, J., Howarth, R. W., Likens, G. E., Matson, P. A., Schindler, D. W.,
Schlesinger, W. H., and Tilman, G. D. 1997b. Human alteration of the global
nitrogen cycle: causes and consequences. Ecological Applications 7, 737-750.
Wackernagel, M. and
Rees, W. Our Ecological Footprint: Reducing Human Impact on Earth New Society
Publishers, Gabriola Island, BC, Canada.
Walgate, R. 2002.
African children talk faster with iron. Bulletin of the World Health
Organization 80, 174.
Wood, S.,
Sebastian, K., and Scherr, S. J. 2000. Pilot Analysis of Global Ecosystems:
Agroecosystems. International Food Policy Research Institute and World
Resources Institute. http://www.ifpri.cgiar.org/pubs/books/page.htm 26.11.01
Endnotes
[1] Klein describes a classic
case-study of ecological imbalance with overpopulation. Two dozen reindeer were
introduced in 1944 onto St. Matthew Island. Lichens were plentiful and there
were no predators. The population increased rapidly, reaching a peak of about
6,000 in 1963. During the heavy snows of 1963-64 almost all of the animals
died, leaving a herd of 41 females and 1 male. The deficiency in food, because
of overgrazing, is thought to have contributed to the high death rate. The
carrying capacity for this species on this island was clearly less than 10,000.
[3] The amount of
nitrogen fixed by humans now exceeds that from natural processes.
[4] With the possible
exception of President Ford (1974-7).
[5] These propositions
are sometimes, characterised as ‘cornucopianism” or “exemptionalism” (Cairns,
1999)
[6] This journal has a
long tradition of championing controversial causes (Kandela, 1998); it also has
a wide international readership, including many health workers in poor countries.
[7] But not the
American literature.
[8] A recent article,
published on the internet, cites Leibenstein (1954).
[9] If the lilies on
the surface of a pond double in area every day, and the pond is covered by day
30, when is the pond half covered?
[10] Rojstaczer et al (2001) came
to similar conclusions.
[11] The Encyclopaedia of Global Population and
Demographics (Ness and Ciments, 1999) has also given substantial credence
to neo-Malthusian arguments.
No comments:
Post a Comment